{"id":1164,"date":"2010-03-01T12:00:18","date_gmt":"2010-03-01T17:00:18","guid":{"rendered":"https:\/\/practicalmattersjournal.ecdsdev.org\/?p=1164"},"modified":"2016-05-31T19:55:47","modified_gmt":"2016-05-31T23:55:47","slug":"if-they-kill-us","status":"publish","type":"post","link":"https:\/\/pmcleanup.ecdsdev.org\/2010\/03\/01\/if-they-kill-us\/","title":{"rendered":"“If They Kill Us, At Least Others Will Have More Time to Get Away”: The Ethics of Risk in Ethnographic Practice"},"content":{"rendered":"
Anthropologists have been addressing the issue of risk in the field since the early 1990s, but have yet to detail on what grounds and in what circumstances such risk is warranted. After surveying developments in epistemology in anthropology, this article makes two challenges to the discipline. The first is to consider the strengths of virtue theory for navigating the relationship between ethnographic particularity and broader moral claims. The second challenge is to engage in conversation with religious agents who themselves demonstrate solidarity with the afflicted in situations of risk. Throughout, I draw on my fieldwork in northern Uganda and South Sudan.1<\/u><\/sup><\/em><\/p>\n \u201cI have a favor to ask.\u201d<\/p>\n I say this in my most importunate voice. I am meeting with Ben Phillips, the Uganda Country Program Director for Catholic Relief Services. We have been in his office for an hour talking about the conflict in northern Uganda. The Lord\u2019s Resistance Army (LRA), early on representative of the Acholi people of the North, has by now abducted between twenty-five and sixty-five thousand people in the region to be porters, soldiers, and sex slaves, and has mutilated or murdered thousands more. The United Peoples Defense Force (UPDF), sent by the government ostensibly to protect the Acholi, has been of little help, and its numbers have committed rights abuses of their own. It can be difficult to get around in the region, and I need Ben\u2019s help.<\/p>\n \u201cLast summer CRS was kind enough to provide a car and driver to get me places around Gulu. I am wondering if it could do the same this trip in the Kitgum and Pader districts. I want to get to some more outlying areas.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cWe could accommodate that. We would need to know your views on travel with UPDF military escort. If you are unwilling to travel with escort, then you would be limited to visiting locations which CRS has assessed as being safe enough to reach without escort.\u201d<\/p>\n I mull over Ben\u2019s words, then answer.<\/p>\n \u201cI think I\u2019ll make other arrangements. Thanks for hearing me out.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cI fully understand.\u201d<\/p>\n We get up from our chairs and, while shaking hands, I ask Ben, mostly out of courtesy after declining his offer, \u201cAny final advice?\u201d<\/p>\n He replies, \u201cIf you are on a road and no one is coming toward you, you are heading directly into the LRA. The people have scattered.\u201d<\/p><\/blockquote>\n * * *<\/p>\n While anthropologists have long faced risk in their fieldwork, it was not until the 1990s that they began to address risk as a particular topic of focus. Jeff Sluka writes that in 1990 he was \u201cthe first anthropologist to publish an article specifically on managing danger in fieldwork as a methodological and subjective issue.\u201d2<\/u><\/sup> That same year, Nancy Howell published Surviving Fieldwork<\/em>.3<\/u><\/sup> Howell had approached the Board of Directors of the American Anthropological Association (AAA) in the mid-1980s about the need to address directly the problem of risk in fieldwork. The Board established an Advisory Panel on Health and Safety and called upon Howell to spearhead it. Both Sluka\u2019s and Howell\u2019s works offer advice\u2014not unlike, \u201cIf you are on the road and no one is coming toward you, you are heading directly into the LRA\u201d\u2014on how to minimize the risk inherent in researching conflict situations.<\/p>\n At around the same point in time\u20141991\u2014Philippe Bourgois published a strong critique of the AAA code of ethics as being too narrow for research in conflict situations. His fieldwork in Central America brought to the fore for him the problem of disinterested research, as defined by the AAA code, in conflict settings where there is an asymmetry of power, and where those without the power are victims of massive human rights violations.4<\/u> <\/sup> What is notable in the article is that, lacking a substantive body of anthropological literature on the ethics of risk in fieldwork, Bourgois needed to turn to a formal organizational code of conduct in order to generate dialogue. While subsequent publications have furthered the conversation in significant ways,5<\/u><\/sup> when discussing the ethics of risk, the discipline of anthropology as a whole appears to move\u2014even bounce\u2014back and forth between giving very specific practical pointers and critiquing the formal code without offering any integrating conversation other than to relate individual experience. Part of this dynamic may well be the legacy of anthropology\u2019s hard-fought-for cultural relativism that grew out of the discipline\u2019s concern about colonialism being embedded in moral discourse. However, as we will see, that very cultural relativism was and is morally driven.<\/p>\n It may well be time for the discipline of anthropology to think about its (often suppressed) modes of moral discourse, and to ask itself what modes best express and facilitate the commitments of its practitioners. My argument in this article moves in three parts. First, I show how the confrontation with risk in fieldwork exposes both the moral drive behind much anthropology to protect and support those people deemed \u201cother\u201d and the lack of coherence between that drive and the epistemological relativism that has predominated in the discipline. I am aware that there is some debate about that relativism,6<\/u><\/sup> but it remains the dominant fallback\u2014and thus often unargued\u2014posture in the discipline. Second, I will make the case that neo-Aristotelian virtue theory provides one\u2014though I am sure not the only\u2014way to ground both engaged commitment to research subjects and moral claims that protect those subjects. In this section, I will not only set out a version of virtue theory but also display it narratively through a series of events in my own fieldwork in Uganda in a story that discloses the limits of my own virtue at the same time that it vivifies the theory. My effort is to show that the Aristotelian\/neo-Aristotelian tradition of virtue theory presents a grammar of moral discourse\u2014with its focus less on a rule-based, juridically centered ethics and more on the living practices of a community\u2014that has much to commend it to the work of anthropologists.7<\/u><\/sup> Finally, I will argue that anthropologists who are seeking to develop coherent moral rationales for their commitment in risk-filled settings would do well to enter into conversation with religious actors in such settings. These latter actors are often familiar with both risk and unpresumptuous discourse in the virtues. The ground of my claim of the possibility of conversation is the strong analogy between the broad virtue of solidarity, often appealed to by engaged anthropologists, and the Christian virtue of love.<\/p>\n It is important that I be explicit about my own positionality at the start. I am trained in Christian theology\u2014or, more precisely, Christian theological ethics\u2014and have been working from an academic setting, the University of Notre Dame, since 1990. Several years ago I had what would not be inaccurate to call a crisis of vocation: I could no longer in good conscience ply my trade while working from only libraries and speaking to only academic guilds. Liberation theology has influenced academic theology sufficiently such that even those practitioners disinclined towards other liberationist themes must recognize the importance of the poor. Still, the poor themselves are rarely allowed to speak, even in liberation theology where the task is most often to speak for those who \u201ccannot speak for themselves.\u201d8<\/u><\/sup> After some time, it became clear to me that the ethnographic methods of anthropology\u2014for instance, participant observation and the open-ended interview\u2014could help provide a corrective to my discipline.<\/p>\n I began work among the Acholi people in northern Uganda in 2005, during the conflict there, and expanded it to include the Acholi in South Sudan in 2007. I have spent about fourteen months on the ground. About half of that time I have lived in Internally Displaced Persons (IDP) camps. In addition, an Acholi colleague and I have seventy digital voice recorders on the ground with locals trained in interview techniques as part of a collaborative project called \u201cAcholi Voices: Democratizing the War Testimony in Northern Uganda.\u201d We are still in the process of gathering, translating, and transcribing interviews. We plan to post them online in January 2011. Finally, in response to local requests, I, together with others, have started a nongovernmental organization (peaceharvest.org) that combines peacebuilding with agricultural training. My field experience has confirmed my methodological misgivings about theology, and I have critiqued my discipline for its shortcomings.9<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n However, if theology and anthropology are to enter into conversation with each other and not simply involve the former poaching ideas from the latter, then it is necessary to interrogate the latter as well. Anthropology, at least with regard to Christian religious traditions, has a specific history that it will need to overcome or at least significantly reinterpret if it is to contribute to and gain from an exchange with theologians.10<\/u><\/sup> There are openings for such conversation, where the discipline moves beyond an anthropologyof<\/em> Christianity to anthropology in conversation with<\/em> Christianity,11<\/u><\/sup> but these openings are rare and constitute a decidedly minority effort. My task, then, is to help widen the openings from the theological side, but in a manner that speaks to anthropologists in terms recognizable to their discipline.<\/p>\n \u201cWhat are you going to do for us?\u201d<\/p>\n It is my last night in Pabbo camp, and I have rejoined the group of men whom I have come to call in my notes the \u201cTeachers\u2019 Drinking Club.\u201d Most of the men are teachers in the secondary school. The camp has not been attacked by the rebels in two years, but a burned-out school bus three kilometers north reminds people that the rebels prefer to set them on fire than to shoot them.<\/p>\n Each night after work, the men of the Teachers\u2019 Drinking Club sit on benches in a circle around a clay urn full of alcoholic mash and drink the brew through four-foot bamboo straws.<\/p>\n \u201cWe know you have your research. But what are you going to do for us?\u201d<\/p>\n Otim is the macro-theorist among the teachers. To him, it is not a matter of the rebels versus the government. \u201cThe white man gives us guns so that we keep busy killing each other,\u201d he said last night. The others looked away, or took another sip of their mash, but none said anything in disagreement. Perhaps they were uncomfortable because they might lose a potential patron. I had promised to see their school tomorrow before heading to Gulu. Otim was and is undaunted. \u201cThen you come and steal our knowledge. You steal our culture. You come and talk to us about our knowledge and our culture and then take it all back with you. And we have nothing left. Look at us. You see how we live. What are you going to do for us?\u201d12<\/u><\/sup><\/p><\/blockquote>\n * * *<\/p>\n In order to investigate how anthropology might broaden its discourse, it is necessary to examine where that discourse has been. We will see, then, how the critique of epistemological relativism has arisen from within anthropology itself. It will also be evident that there is a consistent moral drive that persists through three stages in the development of anthropology, and that engaged anthropology has yet to provide an adequate articulation of the grounds for that drive. In what I would consider a first stage leading to the present situation, methodological<\/em> relativism arises as a moral stance aimed at the protection of the subjects of research. It comes into being in early twentieth-century anthropology\u2014I am thinking here especially of Franz Boas\u2019s 1928Anthropology and Modern Life<\/em>\u2014as a methodology in response and opposition to the unilineal evolutionism of the time.13<\/u><\/sup> As I understand it, unilineal evolutionism accounts for differences between cultures not by pointing to differences in space\u2014\u201cThey are different because they developed over there\u201d\u2014but by constructing differences in time \u2014\u201cThey are different because they are from earlier and lower stages of evolution.\u201d The theory of unilineal evolution justifies and animates racist policies of exploitation. The anthropological studies of Boas and others attempt to look at other cultures \u201cscientifically,\u201d that is, without the cultural triumphalism of unilinear evolutionism. They ground their scientific methodology in an epistemological realism. Racism, in this case, is just not scientific.<\/p>\n With the \u201cinterpretive turn\u201d in the 1980s, however, much of anthropology set aside scientific realism<\/em>. In the absence of an agreed-upon alternative, epistemological<\/em> (and not just methodological) relativism became the assumed norm. The moral concern to protect the subjects of research, however, remained the same. Such concern evidences itself in Clifford Geertz\u2019s 1984 article, \u201cAnti Anti-Relativism\u201d: the primary threat to humanity is not a relativism that claims no truth of the matter, but a universalism that is willing to exploit and harm others on behalf of what is actually a culturally bound understanding of the truth.14<\/u><\/sup> Over twenty years later, many, and perhaps most, anthropologists exhibit the same concern. Robert Ulin writes<\/p>\n I very much agree with Geertz that the problem is less with what is relative and more with arguments advanced in support of absolutes and universals. The challenge posed by reputed universals is more than academic but reaches to the very heart of policy formation and law at the levels of the nation-state and beyond. We simply need to recall the debates in France over the chador or here in America the ethnically charged discussions of policing borders or for that matter the renewal of the \u201cPatriot Act.\u201d15<\/u><\/sup><\/p><\/blockquote>\n At this point, without the scientific realism assumed in Boas\u2019s method, methodological relativism blurs into epistemological relativism.<\/p>\n The moral concern shaping anthropology continues at this point to arise out of a judgment about which is the worse threat to human flourishing: the hegemonic design often resting behind the articulation of universal norms or the nihilism suggested by the claim that no culture can judge any other. As a whole, anthropologists have judged the former to be the worse threat. They often attempt to keep from falling into the latter by making the distinction\u2014as George Marcus and Michael Fischer do\u2014between methodological and doctrinal cultural relativism.16<\/u><\/sup> However, vagueness about and resistance to moral discourse tout courte<\/em> has made doctrinal relativism anthropological orthodoxy. On my reading, this is why after over 160 pages of arguing that there is no simple realism and that all anthropology involves interpretation, Marcus and Fischer break from their narrative\u2014\u201cWe end with a word about the moral or ethical dimension\u2026\u201d\u2014to make the point that anthropology ought not to be involved in the \u201cassertion of values.\u201d17<\/u><\/sup> To \u201cassert values\u201d is to risk being oppressive. Rather, anthropology should simply be about \u201cthe empirical exploration\u201d of the conditions for the articulation of values. In other words, after a full book detailing how there are no simple \u201cfacts,\u201d Marcus and Fischer end with a coda restating the fact (\u201cempirical\u201d)\/value split in order to avoid appearing moralistic and therefore oppressive. Marcus and Fischer\u2019s book is significant in that it is frequently cited as a classic text that brings together and projects into the future the cultural anthropology of the time.18<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n However, critique of this cultural relativism has arisen from within anthropology itself from, among others, researchers working in conflict areas who charge that it is precisely the relativism that is colonial and oppressive. This is what I think of as a third moment\u2014it is too early to tell whether it will become established enough to call it a stage\u2014in anthropology, and it continues the concern with protecting research subjects, now in the context of engaged risk. Philippe Bourgois, for instance, recounts the academic fallout from his reporting of human rights abuses in El Salvador in an article that appears just five years after the Marcus and Fischer volume. Bourgois witnesses a massacre of peasants by the Salvadoran military. He notifies the media and human rights organizations and gives public testimony. \u201cIt was also almost the end of my anthropological career,\u201d he reports, because he had violated several dicta of the AAA\u2019s Code of Ethics, all of which are built around the idea of the objective, non-committed participant observer.19<\/u><\/sup> For instance, reporting the crimes violated the subjects\u2019\u2014including the marauding military\u2019s\u2014right to privacy, and it potentially placed in jeopardy the opportunity for future non-committed scholars to conduct their research. If he had not gone to the media and rights organizations\u2014if he had kept quiet\u2014Bourgois would not have violated the AAA Code in any significant way.<\/p>\n Bourgois responds to the AAA Code by making the case that situations of oppression require a different, broader understanding of ethics. If informed consent remains paramount, then one can never report human rights violations by oppressive regimes. Anthropology, Bourgois argues, is caught in a time-warp where the posture of moral non-commitment still serves to protect threatened cultures. The result is a \u201cpredilection for the exotic\u201d and \u201cpreoccupation with purity.\u201d20<\/u><\/sup> Such a posture ignores the realities of power\u2014both the asymmetrical power between oppressor and oppressed and the social and political power of the researcher. Bourgois points out that the peasants wanted him present and reporting on what was going on because he had power, and doing so would keep them safer by making atrocities public knowledge.<\/p>\n What the non-committed approach to anthropology masks is the fact that cultural relativism assumes considerable power on the part of its bearer: one can afford\u2014economically and politically\u2014to be uninvolved without consequence. The task is to insert oneself into the setting, gather the information\u2014or, as Otim would say it, \u201csteal our culture\u201d\u2014and extract oneself as if never there. From Otim\u2019s standpoint, it is a form of plunder. Cultural relativism is the posture that allows one to do this with a clean conscience. June Nash, writing of her years in conflict-ridden Bolivia and its effect on her view of her research, is unstinting: \u201cThis breakdown of my carefully cultivated \u2018cultural relativist\u2019 position forced me to realize that it was premised on a colonialist attitude\u2026 We can no longer retreat into the deceptive pose of neutrality.\u201d21<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n Just how widespread this latest moment of socially active commitment to research subjects is in anthropology is difficult to assess, because the discipline itself gives mixed signals. On the one hand, there are the writings of committed scholars, such as those collected in the recent volume, Engaged Observer: Anthropology, Advocacy, and Activism<\/em>,22<\/u><\/sup> and the fact that the 2008 American Anthropological Association annual meeting took as its theme, \u201cInclusion, Collaboration, and Engagement\u201d; on the other hand, in 1998 the AAA revised its earlier Code of Ethics from the claim that \u201canthropologists bear a positive responsibility to speak out publicly,\u201d23<\/u><\/sup> to the far weaker statement: \u201cAnthropological researchers should make the results of their research appropriately available to sponsors, students, decisionmakers, and other non-anthropologists\u2026 Anthropologists may choose to move beyond disseminating research results to a position of advocacy. This is an individual decision, but not an ethical responsibility.\u201d24<\/u><\/sup> In other words, according to the 1998 code of ethics, Bourgois would have remained an anthropologist in good standing had he not reported the military atrocities to the media in a timely fashion, but rather published his research in a peer-reviewed article that found comparatively narrow readership in the AAA a year or more later.<\/p>\n The overall trajectory of anthropology, then, has gone from methodological relativism to epistemological relativism to, at least among some practitioners, an engaged anthropology that is as of yet unclear about its method and epistemology. There is a tension at the center of engaged anthropology that it must confront if it is to convince the rest of the discipline to practice its forms of commitment. One pull of the tension is the awareness of the position and power of the researcher, an awareness that has led to the rejection of the possibility of both epistemological and political neutrality. We always observe and speak from somewhere in particular. This emphasis on the researcher\u2019s positionality is the pull towards epistemological relativism. The call of engaged anthropology is for the researcher to locate herself, insofar as this is possible, among and for those people who are marginalized and oppressed. The other pull is that, in order to both identify and resist situations of oppression, engaged observers find that they must appeal to the language of universal human rights, and this is the pull towards epistemological realism.25<\/u><\/sup> Bourgois is forceful: \u201cTo reiterate, the problem [of anthropological disengagement] is rooted in a specifically North American epistemology of relativism and \u2018value-free science\u2019 which forbids engaged research and\u2014when taken to its logical conclusion\u2014denies absolute assertions including those of universal human rights.\u201d26<\/u><\/sup> Others, such as Dana-Ain Davis, follow suit in asserting that engaged anthropology is \u201cgrounded in principles of inclusion, equal rights, and equal access.\u201d27<\/u><\/sup> What is lacking in the literature, however, is an account of how perspectival particularity in fact links with and grounds broad\u2014indeed, universal\u2014moral claims.<\/p>\n Engaged anthropology needs to work out how it is going to keep these two pulls in tension, and not let one dominate the other. Absent a discussion linking epistemological particularity with broader claims about the way persons ought to relate to one another and how society ought to be ordered, engaged anthropology threatens to perpetuate the very problems it tries to overcome. Precisely through its solidarity with the oppressed, engaged anthropology seeks to move beyond the idea of the exoticized other; however, without nuanced moral reasoning about that commitment, it may simply reproduce the binary relationship of self over against other, only this time along the lines of oppressed (and those who stand with them) versus oppressor, thus redacting out of any narrative the detailed complexity that fieldwork is positioned to highlight. Bourgois warns that \u201cthe ethics of anthropological research are too complicated and important to be reduced to unambiguous absolutes or even perhaps to be clearly defined.\u201d28<\/u><\/sup> Regarding her experience in Bolivia, June Nash observes that \u201cnot all actions in the name of revolution were revolutionary.\u201d29<\/u><\/sup> Without more careful reasoning, engaged anthropology risks essentializing both oppressor and oppressed.30<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n Perhaps worse, if engaged anthropologists do not provide careful linkages between their perspectivalism and their moral and political claims, they have no coherent way to challenge those researchers disinclined to accept these latter claims. Again, the 1998 revision of the AAA Code of Ethics states that reporting human rights abuses in a timely fashion to the media so that the public is made aware and can respond before other atrocities ensue is,\u201cnot an ethical responsibility,\u201d but rather is an \u201cindividual decision.\u201d The change in the Code was long in coming. The rise in the numbers of anthropologists working for either governments or private companies brought debate regarding the Code in the mid-1980s. James Downs\u2019 letter to the AAA Newsletter<\/em> is representative of the pressure. Anthropologists working for governments must \u201cplay by the rules of the game,\u201d which includes non-disclosure of facts that might discomfort one\u2019s employer. So, too, with the private sector: firms \u201cexist to sell knowledge,\u201d and the information one gathers, regardless of its content, belongs to them. Downs not only fails to resist the pressure, he gets swept up in it in a manner consistent with doctrinal relativism: any prohibition against secret research \u201cfails to take into account the realities of today\u2019s world\u2026 I welcome a Code of Ethics which considers such [classified] work a matter of personal choice.\u201d31<\/u><\/sup> Absent a more richly developed moral discourse, engaged anthropologists lack any way of making the case that Downs is wrong. Given the government use of anthropologists in the United States war in Iraq, there remains an intense need for making just such a case.<\/p>\n Just as ethnographic method is not a cure-all for the ills of theology, virtue theory is not a panacea for the shortcomings of anthropology. In what follows, I put forward a version of virtue theory because it has advantages over the major alternative forms of moral reasoning as articulated by philosophical and theological ethics. The point here is not that virtue theory provides a kind of algorithmic calculus for what anthropologists ought to do in particular situations; rather, it provides a grammar\u2014in terms of certain communal practices taking place within and understood in light of overall narratives\u2014which facilitates moral discernment through ethnographic encounter. Because of the importance of descriptive detail, it is necessary not just to set out a virtue theory<\/em> but to offer a display<\/em> of what ethnographic discernment in light of virtue might look like. In what follows, I take on each of these tasks in turn.<\/p>\n Moral philosophy offers three main forms of normative theory\u2014deontology (Kant and Rawls), utilitarianism (Bentham, Mill, and Singer), and virtue theory (Aristotle, Hume, Anscombe, Foote, and MacIntyre). The first two theories present major obstacles to their operating as modes of moral reasoning for the engaged anthropologist. Both deontology and utilitarianism abstract from the particulars of communal life in order to develop binding moral norms. Attention to particulars detracts, according to these approaches, from precision in moral reasoning by adding contingent factors that limit the otherwise universal applicability of the norms. Thus the Kantian, John Rawls, arrives at his criterion of fairness by positioning his fictive moral agents behind a \u201cveil of ignorance\u201d where they know nothing of their particular lives before he allows them to choose the kinds of lives they want to lead, and the utilitarian Peter Singer disallows consideration of any of our attachments to particular people in the calculation of distributive justice.32<\/u><\/sup> For utilitarians, what counts is only the greatest amount of happiness in the abstracted aggregate. To whatever degree one may agree or disagree with the conclusions of deontologists or utilitarians on specific issues, their methodologies of assuming or inventing a moral agent who reasons from nowhere in particular makes them a difficult match for a discipline that gives central place to the method of participant observation in particular cultures.<\/p>\n It would be of hollow comfort if virtue theories provided the best approach to moral reasoning for anthropologists simply because the other two available options were unusable. Fortunately, there is much in virtue theories to commend them. Many and perhaps most contemporary virtue theorists emphasize persons\u2019 embeddedness in particular communities. This is due in large part to the greater focus in virtue theories on the continuity of the agent as distinct from the discreet acts that the agent might perform. To make sense of the continuity of the agent, one has to attend to her relationships with other persons in her culture and society. In the preferred term of anthropology, virtue theory attends to the theorist\u2019s \u201cpositionality.\u201d The moral philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre writes, \u201cIt is not clear to me how any<\/em> adequate philosophical analysis in this area could escape being also a sociological hypothesis, and vice versa<\/em>. There seems something deeply mistaken in the notion enforced by the conventional curriculum that there are two distinct subjects or disciplines\u2014moral philosophy, a set of conceptual inquiries, on the one hand, and the sociology of morals, a set of empirical hypotheses and findings, on the other.\u201d33<\/u> <\/sup> MacIntyre goes further to call for finely detailed cultural interpretations. \u201cWhat we need here is not only philosophical acuteness but also the kind of vision which anthropologists at their best bring to the observation of other cultures.\u201d34<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n It is precisely the lack of embeddedness that leads deontological and utilitarian approaches to take as their specific object the conformity of discreet acts to abstract principles. This is because there is no other basis of continuity of the moral self. Virtue theories, because of their embeddedness, do not create a separate sphere of the \u201cmoral\u201d; moral excellences are analogous to other types of excellences, including in sports and the arts. Moreover, for Aristotle there are both intellectual and moral \u201cvirtues.\u201d Therefore, the usual translation of the Greek arete<\/em> as \u201cvirtue\u201d is perhaps better rendered \u201cexcellence\u201d to convey the breadth of the term, and this is the case particularly given present distortions of the concept. The development of modern society and the autonomous self-legislating individual loses contact with the fact of human communal embeddedness. As a result, its moral rules cannot be grounded in the patterns of societal interaction, but only in abstractions. The \u201cmoral\u201d becomes a separate sphere directed only by abstract principles and geared only towards the production of laws. In this context, virtue theories themselves degenerate, such that a \u201cvirtue\u201d becomes simply a disposition to obey a particular rule or law.<\/p>\n It is in this historical context that the discipline of anthropology itself arises. It is no wonder, then, that its earlier practitioners such as Boas view themselves as \u201cscientists\u201d\u2014in other words, persons with intellectual virtues\u2014over against the harsh colonial moralism of the time. In doing so, however, they reinforce the fact\/value split presupposed by modernity. The result is studies that fail to take into account how the social positionality of the researcher shapes interpretation. Moreover, given the nervousness of anthropology about its own complicity in colonialism, even when the discipline in theory comes to recognize the role of interpretation, it, as we have seen with Marcus and Fischer, still refuses to recognize the role of values in that interpretation. Fact and value have necessarily come back together, but anthropologists who follow Marcus and Fischer still do not know what to do with the \u201cvalue\u201d dimension of the mix because, in the historical development of their discipline, they have come to identify value simply with a separated realm of \u201cmorals.\u201d For Marcus and Fischer, values are something that an anthropologist can only unidirectionally assert (and thus are to be avoided). As a result, they often cling to a doctrinal cultural relativism even though that relativism is no longer epistemologically intelligible given the discipline\u2019s awareness that there are no simple \u201cfacts.\u201d In response, engaged anthropology presses for universal values as encoded in human rights, but as of yet has not formed a language to link rights with ethnographic particularity.<\/p>\n Contemporary virtue theories hold promise for anthropology in large part because they have arisen not only as an effort to recontextualize moral reasoning in close social and cultural analysis, but also as a protest against the idea that there is an entirely separate realm of \u201cthe moral\u201d\u2014an idea which has tended to repulse anthropologists. Elizabeth Anscombe, in a 1958 article widely regarded as inaugurating the move to virtue theory in contemporary moral philosophy, argues that the idea of a separate realm of the moral is so ensconced in both our culture and philosophical reasoning that, for the time being, philosophers ought to banish the word \u201cmoral\u201d from their work, and indeed to stop doing \u201cmoral philosophy\u201d altogether, until they can aright their distorted view of the person as free of embeddedness. \u201cThe expressions \u2018moral obligation\u2019, \u2018the moral ought\u2019, and \u2018duty\u2019 are best put on the Index.\u201d35<\/u><\/sup> Anscombe is not suggesting that we should get rid of the language of \u201cought\u201d altogether, only eschew the idea that \u201cmoral ought\u201d is different in kind from other kinds of excellences. \u201cIt may be possible, if we are resolute, to discard the term \u2018morally ought\u2019, and simply return to the ordinary \u2018ought\u2019, which, we ought to notice, is such an extremely frequent term of human language that it is difficult to imagine getting on without it.\u201d36<\/u><\/sup> Anscombe, like MacIntyre, views moral obligation as strongly analogous with other types of obligation\u2014\u201cHe ought to have passed the ball\u201d\u2014with this difference: she views the language of \u201cmoral\u201d as so corrupted that philosophers ought to discard it until they get their understanding of the person right. MacIntyre, writing over twenty years later, and at much greater explanatory length, risks using the term by taking the space to detail a version of virtue theory. With both Anscombe and MacIntyre, as well as with a host of other virtue theorists, we see that they offer an approach to interpretation that neither denies the role of value nor draws upon a concept of \u201cthe moral\u201d that serves as a lever for oppressive dismissal of cultural pluralism. The person\u2014who is, among other things, a moral agent\u2014is always and everywhere embedded in particular communities such that the word \u201cought\u201d\u2014let alone moral and legal rules\u2014is not something that one can simply apply from the outside. Though hardly failsafe, this characteristic of virtue theory builds in a resistance to the kind of ethnocentrism that most contemporary anthropologists rightly abhor.<\/p>\n With these advantages of virtue theories in mind, we can now say a bit more about just what constitutes a virtue. Then I will be able to offer a scenario and try to display what a virtue analysis might look like\u2014one that is at once anthropological and moral. To detail what constitutes a virtue, I make reference to MacIntyre\u2019s book After Virtue<\/em>, which many interpreters identify as a locusclassicus<\/em> of contemporary virtue theory. The text is all the more interesting for our purposes because it came out in the early 1980s, just at the time when anthropologists were questioning the fact\/value separation from the other side of the divide.<\/p>\n MacIntyre builds his understanding of virtue around two key concepts, that of a practice and that of the narrative quest. He defines a practice as \u201cany coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative human activity through which goods internal to the activity are realized in the course of trying to achieve those standards of excellence which are appropriate to, and partially derived from, that form of activity.\u201d37<\/u><\/sup> MacIntyre gives both athletic (football) and aesthetic (portrait painting) examples of what constitutes a practice and views them as analogous to moral practices. Key to his concept of excellence in the performance of a practice is the distinction between goods internal to the practice and those that, while supportive and even necessary, are external to it. The University of Notre Dame\u2019s contract with adidas may provide some of the financial support that enables the school to participate in Division I football, but it is not internal to the practice of football like the crisp route-running of wide receiver Golden Tate. In light of this understanding of practice, MacIntyre sets out an initial definition of virtue as \u201can acquired human quality the possession and exercise of which tends to enable us to achieve those goods which are internal to practices and the lack of which effectively prevents us from achieving such goods.\u201d38<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n Classical Aristotelian virtue theory provides the concept of a telos<\/em> as a way of ordering the array of virtues that arise in and further develop practices. The problem with Aristotle\u2019s account of the telos, however, is not only that he grounds it in an untenable metaphysical biology, but also that it is closed-ended and therefore overdetermines the content of the life of excellence. The endpoint of the teleological journey is fixed in a way that pre-sets all of the relationships within it. If all virtue theory necessarily followed in this vein, it would signal the end of any usefulness for an engaged anthropology. The turn to doctrinal cultural relativism in much of anthropology was driven precisely by a determination to avoid, again rightly, the closed-ended teleology of unilinear evolutionism. The biology of unilinear evolutionism is different from Aristotle\u2019s, but the results for moral reasoning are the same.<\/p>\n MacIntyre explicitly rejects Aristotle\u2019s biological grounding and offers in its stead the idea of the narrative quest. He argues that human life is unintelligible without the context of narrative: \u201cNarrative history of a certain kind turns out to be the basic and essential genre for the characterization of human actions.\u201d39<\/u><\/sup> It is important to recognize, however, that lived<\/em> narratives are open-ended, both because they are subject to communal contestation and because future events will shape and reshape our understanding of what constitutes the life well lived. MacIntyre draws on the concept of a quest to express both the contestation and the open-endedness. The idea of a quest is \u201cnot at all that of a search for something already adequately characterized\u2026. A quest is always an education both as to the character of that which is sought and in self-knowledge.\u201d40<\/u><\/sup> This understanding of a quest and furthering self-understanding fits well with the recent emphasis in anthropology on the self-reflexivity and even autobiography inherent in interpretation.41<\/u><\/sup> In light of his concept of the narrative quest, MacIntyre provides a further detailed definition of the virtues as \u201cthose dispositions which will not only sustain practices and enable us to achieve the goods internal to practices, but will sustain us in the relevant kind of quest for the good, by enabling us to overcome the harms, dangers, temptations and distractions which we encounter, and which will furnish us with increasing self-knowledge and increasing knowledge of the good\u201d.42<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n MacIntyre\u2019s account of virtue is not uncontested, even among virtue theorists, but what I have outlined thus far is enough to provide a context within which to display what engaged anthropology might look like when infused with the grammar of a virtue analysis. Again, the argument thus far has been that anthropologists have long been driven by a moral concern to protect their often-marginalized research subjects. At one point the presumed epistemological posture for such ends was one form or another of relativism. Recently, however, anthropologists working in situations of risk have found that such epistemological relativism is inadequate for the kinds of rights claims necessary to protect subjects. I have been offering a version of virtue theory as a form of moral reasoning that can hold together both attention to cultural particularity and the need to make broader moral claims. In the following section, I do a moral-ethnographic discernment of events in my fieldwork as a way of displaying what virtue analysis might look like. We will find that, as any close ethnographic analysis should, the narrative complexifies oppressor\/oppressed interpretations without doing away with them.<\/p>\n \u201cWait. How much longer are you here?\u201d<\/p>\n Ocena Charles\u2019s question catches me by surprise. We have been talking about the various practices of Acholi culture\u2014the otole mock-fight dance, the fact that funerals can last days, even weeks\u2014for more than an hour at the Victoria restaurant in Entebbe<\/p>\n \u201cI leave tomorrow morning,\u201d I answer.<\/p>\n Ocena sits back and looks out over the water of Lake Victoria, pondering my answer for a long moment. He turns to me.<\/p>\n \u201cHow much time do you have before you need to get back to Kampala tonight?\u201d<\/p>\n Another clearly-stated yet elliptical question.<\/p>\n \u201cI have nothing planned. I just need to get back early enough so that I can get up on time for my plane in the morning.\u201d<\/p>\n He looks back out over the lake, nods his head, and then turns to me once more.<\/p>\n \u201cI have some documents for you. Will you take some documents for me to the United States?\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cWhat kind of documents?\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cFor your research.\u201d He is still speaking in code. The documents are, he says, for me, but I am to take them to the United States for him. \u201cYou can use them for your research.\u201d<\/p>\n He does not fully trust me yet, but he trusts me enough to be his courier.<\/p>\n \u201cYes, I will take them.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cAnd you know that you cannot tell anyone that they are from me.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cYes.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cOr else the government will\u2026\u201d He makes a slicing movement across his neck.<\/p>\n My risks are far less serious in this instance, but they are real. If I am found out, the government may not let me back in the country. Carrying what is ostensibly for my research may cost me my research. It will not be the first time the government refuses re-entry to an undesirable. My employer, the University of Notre Dame, in keeping with its hard-won status as a newly arrived national university, takes a dim view of those who do not finish their research and produce \u201cthe book,\u201d regardless of how much I may use my academic skills for humanitarian purposes.<\/p>\n We get a car and driver, and Ocena explains why we are heading away from his place in Entebbe. \u201cI have to keep the documents at my nephew\u2019s place, or else they will find them and kill me.\u201d<\/p>\n We drive out to a Kampala slum and he gets out of the car. I am not sure whether we have taken our circuitous route because of possible danger or simply because that is the way the streets are laid out. To our left, shacks of corrugated metal compete for coveted space. The adults continually duck their heads so as not to cut them on the edges of the roofs, and so look like they are joining the bobbing chickens around their feet.<\/p>\n In less than five minutes, he is back. He opens the back door, gets in, and puts a brown file folder with an elastic restraining strap around it on my lap.<\/p>\n \u201cRead it later.\u201d<\/p>\n We drive away.43<\/u><\/sup><\/p><\/blockquote>\n * * *<\/p>\n The virtue theory I have been setting out frames its moral reasoning in terms of narrative, and it is not difficult to interpret the colonial and post-colonial history of the Acholi people of northern Uganda whom I study as a narrative of being on the receiving end of oppression. In his anthropological work on the Acholi, Sverker Finnstrom refers to them as \u201cthe abject of the abject.\u201d44<\/u><\/sup>Prior to the arrival of the British, the people in northern Uganda who came to be known as the Acholi were loosely federated and decentralized.45<\/u><\/sup> In 1894 the British named Uganda a protectorate and in 1896 included the people of northern Uganda in this designation. That Uganda was a protectorate and not a colony is critical because in the former the British dominate through \u201cindirect\u201d rule, that is, by designating one indigenous group to rule over the rest on behalf of the empire. Indirect rule, coupled with the British quest for bureaucratic order, hardened and reified ethnic differences by setting African over against African.46<\/u><\/sup> The British made the Bugandans in the South, who already had a centralized political system that more closely resembled that of the colonizers, the administrators of the protectorate.<\/p>\n Over one hundred ten years later, a form of indirect rule continues. President Museveni\u2019s National Resistance Movement government receives over half of its budget from foreign aid in a way that reinforces his twenty-four-year presidency and lack of democratic accountability. (In the last campaign, he jailed his main opponent, Kissa Besigye, on trumped up charges of rape and treason). What is taking place in Uganda today is de facto<\/em> indirect rule by the donor nations. They get a president who meets their strategic interests, and he gets to rule in perpetuity. When the Acholi resistance failed in 1987 and then imploded in the 1990s with the Lord\u2019s Resistance Army abducting and mutilating its own people, the Museveni government not only failed to provide sufficient counterforce to protect the Acholi, but also forcefully displaced them into so-called \u201cprotected\u201d camps that actually served as magnets for LRA attack. The WHO estimated in 2005\u2014when over 90 percent of the Acholi lived in camps\u2014that there were 1000 excess deaths per week (deaths in excess of what would be the case under \u201cnormal\u201d conditions for the region) due to malnutrition, disease, and violence.47<\/u><\/sup> This, and an array of direct human rights violations in the North on the part of the Ugandan military,48<\/u><\/sup> has made the charge of genocide against Museveni and his National Resistance Movement ruling government a prominent, even if suppressed, Acholi interpretation of the conflict.49<\/u><\/sup> Freedom from this oppression is an overarching telos<\/em>, and international publication of the actions of the NRM is a key means of furthering progress towards that end.<\/p>\n This is the narrative I stepped into when I began doing my research in northern Uganda in 2005, and I came to it with a narrative of my own. For fifteen years, I had been teaching Catholic social ethics with an emphasis on issues of armed conflict and the gap between rich and poor, and had become increasingly convinced that the main mode of investigation in the discipline\u2014library research\u2014was seriously inadequate for both epistemological and theological reasons.50<\/u><\/sup> Like many engaged anthropologists,51<\/u><\/sup> I found the incentive and reward system of the academy\u2014with its emphasis on paper presentations at guild conferences, articles in refereed journals, and university press books\u2014to be too narrow to measure the practice of an excellence in a life worth living. Writing on the poor and afflicted seemed to me to require a more robust commitment to them, and that meant engaged participant observation in places\u2014namely, IDP camps\u2014that would take me far outside of my comfort zone. In the language of virtue theory, then, I was seeking to live a more committed practice of solidarity with people who were marginalized in the context of a narrative structured by oppressor\/oppressed dynamics.<\/p>\n My experience in the camps reinforced for me the Acholi\u2019s interpretation of themselves as oppressed and marginalized. While I was helping nuns feed those whom the United Nations Food Program did not reach and who were on the edge of starvation, the NRM\u2019s main concern, as it often is for oppressive regimes with regard to anthropologists,52<\/u><\/sup> was whether I was a spy. In the meantime, they were spying on me.<\/p>\n * * *<\/p>\n The Government Security Officer or \u201cGiSO\u201d of Obul IDP camp, Olweny Benedict stops me on the main road through the camp. \u201cYou have failed to see me.\u201d I am the only muno\u2014white person\u2014of the twenty-two thousand people here, and not easy to miss.<\/p>\n \u201cI stopped by your compound twice. You weren\u2019t there,\u201d I answer. The GiSO\u2019s responsibility for camp security includes control of the flow of public information. He does not like my response.<\/p>\n \u201cSo, you have still failed to see me.\u201d<\/p>\n Olweny appears to be in his forties, though it is hard to tell. It is eight-thirty in the morning and his eyes are already bloodshot on yellow.<\/p>\n \u201cI have direct contact with the President\u201d he continues. \u201cI can call him whenever I want. If he is in London, whenever. I have been an intelligence officer for fifteen years, including in Sudan. That is why they have me here. Obul is close to Sudan. It is not even ten miles. Some people come here and say bad things about Obul. And you?\u201d Olweny asks. \u201cWhat shall I say you are doing here?\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cI am an academic. I am studying traditional Acholi religion.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cSo we cooperate. I have to tell the higher command what you are up to. They already know that you are here. They wonder, \u2018What is the muno doing in Lokung?\u2019 Now I can tell them what you are doing. They had some mistaken ideas.\u201d<\/p>\n That afternoon, two young men show up outside my quarters while I am writing up the morning\u2019s field notes. They ask, seemingly in passing, about my plans. I have not met them before, though they pull up chairs. Okumu, my host and a member of the opposition party, has warned me about the possibility: \u201cAnyone who asks how long you are staying, do not tell them. Give them a vague answer to throw them off. Acholi do not ask how long a guest is staying. It is against hospitality. If they ask, they are spies. If they ask what you are doing, just tell them that you are doing your research and helping with the church.\u201d They do not, as most visitors do, ask for my financial assistance.53<\/u><\/sup><\/p><\/blockquote>\n * * *<\/p>\n The history of virtue theories is also a history of different tables of the virtues. The classical tradition enumerated four cardinal\u2014from the Latin, cardo<\/em>, meaning fundamental, the thing on which other things hinge\u2014virtues: courage, justice, temperance, and prudence. Christianity added the theological virtues of faith, hope, and love. There have been variations on both of these lists. The term that engaged anthropologists draw on most, however, appears to be \u201csolidarity,\u201d and I will focus on this virtue. Pope John Paul II characterizes solidarity as a virtue involving the \u201cfirm and persevering determination to commit oneself to the common good.\u201d54<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n My first efforts at solidarity\u2014other than the simple fact of being there in the camps, which many Acholi told me itself gave them some hope\u2014were activities of the sort that Christian traditions have described as the works\u2014or in the language we have been using, the practices\u2014of mercy: feed the hungry and clothe the naked in direct, low-level daily interaction. When a friend in the United States gave me $5,000 to \u201cuse in any way that you think will help the Acholi,\u201d I raised more funds and, with others, put together a month-long pilot project that coupled peacebuilding with the provision of oxen and training in their innovative use for a region that had lost 98% of their working livestock to the conflict. We have now formed the nongovernmental organization PeaceHarvest (peaceharvest.org<\/u>).<\/p>\n Still, Ocena\u2019s request to ferry documents raised questions as to the depth and kind of my commitment. The fact that the government had already positioned me in the social context of its distrust and that I had interviewed people who had been tortured by its operatives\u2014one man had a cord that was attached to the ceiling tied to his genitals and was forced to jump off of a box\u2014inclined me to accept the request. June Nash\u2019s words rang loud in my head: in such a setting, \u201cneutrality\u201d is untenable. It seemed that committing myself to the common good, and the marginalized in particular, would require even more of me than I previously thought.<\/p>\n However, if virtue theories provide the grammar to ground and even justify my action in accepting the documents, they also offer the language to critique it. The dominant Acholi narrative is not without its problems. Many Acholi served in the military in Milton Obote\u2019s regime, which preceded Museveni\u2019s, and participated in atrocities committed by that regime in a region called the Luwero Triangle. When I ask Acholis about the atrocities, the most frequent answer I receive\u2014as if Nuremberg did not exist\u2014is that Acholis did not constitute the officer corps that gave the orders. Moreover, given that the majority of the direct attacks on the Acholi from 1988 onward have been from the Acholi-led and dominated LRA, the charge that it is Museveni\u2019s regime that is singularly involved in genocide loses its credibility. Without unweighting the severity of the activities of the NRM and those who act on its behalf\u2014and certainly without suggesting in any way that the Acholi, as some would have it, deserve their fate\u2014careful analysis of the narratives at minimum complicates the oppressor\/oppressed rubric.<\/p>\n Moreover, performing the works of mercy is one kind of practice, serving as a courier of sensitive documents is another, and sets the agent\u2014me\u2014in a web of intrigue in a way that acts like feeding the hungry do not. Ocena knew the risks better than I did, and yet he requested, in a manner that was far from straightforward, that I undertake them. He would not tell me what was in the documents. It was \u201cfor your research.\u201d He did not tell me who he wanted me to deliver the documents to until I had arrived in the United States, and he e-mailed me from a third party. For my part, though, I do not regret taking the documents. I took them not knowing the full range of the possible implications of my actions. After I had left for the United States, one of the several extra-constitutional secret service groups Museveni has formed demanded entry into the compound of the religious community with which I had been staying and insisted on seeing the guest registry. The government had been listening in on the phone calls between Ocena and me, with the result that I had inadvertently drawn in unsuspecting people. It caused havoc in the community. Aristotle writes that experience is necessary to develop the phronesis<\/em>, or practical wisdom\u2014itself an intellectual virtue\u2014necessary to direct the moral virtues. I had the desire to practice the moral virtue of solidarity but overestimated\u2014willfully so, I think\u2014my ability to direct it.<\/p>\n Through use of this scenario, I hope that we can see how the grammar of \u201cnarrative\u201d and \u201cpractice,\u201d provided by virtue theories and coupled with what Clifford Geertz calls a \u201cthick description\u201d of a situation, offers a way for engaged anthropologists to enter into moral discourse and assessment in a way that directs their practices without being moralizing. It combines socio-cultural and philosophical analysis in a way that not only overcomes the fact-value split, but also shows the latter to be the fiction that it is. It seems, then, that virtue theory can attend to the concern among many anthropologists for solidarity with research subjects while attending to both cultural particularity and the need to make broader moral claims.<\/p>\n It is important, however, to take the demonstration further. We have seen how situations of risk raise the issue of moral reasoning for anthropology. Now I would like to take that reasoning and place it back into a situation of risk where not only the researcher\u2019s project, but also her life is at stake. Not many of us experience such situations, and the question remains how to gain practical wisdom here. In the virtue tradition, one learns through experience, which means, as in my case, making mistakes. The problem is that situations where one\u2019s life is at risk do not permit of mistakes. How then are we to learn? Virtue theories draw on the idea of exemplars: we can learn through reading about\u2014or, better, watching\u2014persons who exemplify practical wisdom in living out the virtues. With regard to situations where one\u2019s life is at risk, both engaged anthropologists and religious persons who live in solidarity with the abject have experience, and both can benefit from ongoing exchange with one another. The ensuing conversation is not simply beneficial for its own sake, but also because with the emphasis on the particular in virtue theories, there are no universals\u2014including human rights\u2014in the abstract. The only way to ground universal, or at least cross-cultural, claims is through the difficult process of dialogue and even cooperation between traditions of practice.55<\/u><\/sup> In what follows, the strong analogies between solidarity broadly understood and Christian charity allow one instance of this dialogue to take place.<\/p>\n I have never seen a night sky like this. There are no cities near Magwi, South Sudan, and so no light pollution. I see now that there are stars between the main, brightest stars, and stars between the ones in between\u2014many more and much brighter than I could have imagined. We are sitting outside in plastic chairs in something of a circle in the compound of the Eucharistic Center where conversation has yet to be displaced by television. Father Joseph Otto and the health unit workers, Dominick and Odoch, bounce from topic to topic, fed by the day\u2019s events, and my attention shifts from sky to conversation to sky again.<\/p>\n Seemingly without topical prompt, a debate breaks out among them regarding the best direction to run during an LRA attack. Dominick, a slender Madi from Adjumani, argues that it is best to run across the line of fire, to what appears to be off to the side of the attack. Father Joseph disagrees. He holds up his hand in the shape of a C and presses it forward.<\/p>\n \u201cThey attack you like this. The two sides first. They try to catch you at the back, but if you run to the side, they will catch you also. This is how they attacked in January. Ay, yi, yi,\u201d he laughs, shaking his head. \u201cJanuary was the worst month.\u201d Dominick and Odoch tag-team the next few lines.<\/p>\n \u201cAy, last January was bad. It was my first month here.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cThe SPLA was not here yet. They did not come until Easter.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cThere was no one to protect us.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cYou could not go a day without hearing gunshots. You would hear bombs. You would see fires.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cIt was dry season, and the fires would set off bombs \u2014 unexploded ordnance from the war with Khartoum.\u201d<\/p>\n \u201cYou just didn\u2019t know. You would see somebody one day, and the next they\u2019d be dead. Like those men who bought those parts for the Land Cruiser. On the way home they were killed.\u201d<\/p>\n Father Joseph continues his story.<\/p>\n \u201cThe LRA attacked. People from all around came to our compound. They were saying, \u2018Father Joseph, the LRA are coming! Help us!\u2019 I did not know what to do. We couldn\u2019t protect them. Father Maurice was here. So I asked him what we should do. He said, \u2018Let\u2019s get a motorcycle and ride towards the LRA. Let\u2019s try to talk to them. Maybe they\u2019ll talk. And if they kill us, at least the others will have more time to get away.\u201d<\/p>\n The next day, Father Joseph and I drive to Torit to see the bishop. Though the Magwi County Commissioner says that they have all gone to Western Equatoria, the LRA are still around. Father Maurice saw one running from the SPLA earlier in the week, and next week four will be spotted in Agoro, Uganda, just south of the Sudan border, while I am there. Father Joseph crosses himself and says a prayer before he starts the car. I ask him what went through his mind when Father Maurice suggested riding a motorcycle towards the center of an LRA attack.<\/p>\n \u201cWe were the only ones. The SPLA was not there to protect. They did not come until after Easter. And the people, they are just people of the village. They did not know what to do. There are no activists, no community leaders. There is no one who can be in the middle and try to talk with the LRA. Someone maybe they can trust. It is hard. These LRA are not very dependable. But I am a man of peace, and so I seek to make peace wherever I am. I am a priest, and I am supposed to be an image of Christ. So we just got on the motorcycle and went.\u201d<\/p><\/blockquote>\n * * *<\/p>\n When I ask in my conversations with graduate students and assistant professors of anthropology what persons and texts they hold up as exemplars, two of the most frequent responses are Phillipe Bourgois and Nancy Scheper-Hughes, and their books, In Search of Respect and Death Without Weeping<\/em>.56<\/u><\/sup> To be sure, neither Bourgois nor Scheper-Hughes seeks to position themselves as exemplars. I suspect that they might well cringe at the suggestion that they are such. Still, that is one sign of their status of being exemplars, because, as MacIntyre points out, the person of excellence carries out the practices for the sake of the practices themselves, and not for some external good like attention from the discipline. I have commented enough on Bourgois above, and so here will focus on Scheper-Hughes to make the case that there are sufficient analogues between anthropological solidarity and Christian love of neighbor that a conversation between the practitioners of each would be fruitful for both parties.<\/p>\n I am aware that the very suggestion that there are analogues between engaged anthropology and committed Christianity may lead some, perhaps even many, anthropologists, to reject engaged anthropology altogether. The charge would be that it confirms their suspicions that engaged anthropology is necessarily moralistic. If what I have argued thus far is true, however, that charge cannot be made without assuming and retreating back into an untenable fact\/value separation grounded in an unintelligible doctrinal relativism.<\/p>\n I am calling upon the discipline of engaged anthropology to move beyond an objectivist anthropology of<\/em> Christianity to an anthropology in conversation with<\/em> Christianity, not least because many of the discipline\u2019s subjects are themselves Christian. I should make clear as well that my use of the example of the religious tradition of Christianity is not because of any special salvific status on its part\u2014I am sure that similar analogues can be found in other religious traditions\u2014but because it is the tradition I know best as a professional, and because it is, in a form syncretized with traditional Acholi culture and religion, the most practiced among the people I study. Finally and most importantly, as shown above, the only way engaged anthropology can move towards the kind of universal claims that it wants to make regarding human rights is through conversations in a search for analogues with other communities, even those which have historically been considered its enemy.<\/p>\n Scheper-Hughes writes about how the demands of her research subjects that she cease simply observing their activity and join in the aims of their community prompts her turn to a committed anthropology. The impoverished women whom she had been studying in Brazilian shanty towns \u201cturn[ed] their anger against me. Why had I refused to work with them when they had been so willing to work with me? \u2026 I backed away saying\u2026\u2018I cannot be an anthropologist and a companheira<\/em> at the same time.\u2019\u2026.And they gave me an ultimatum: the next time I came back to the Alto do Cruzeiro it would be on their terms, that is, as acompanheira<\/em>, \u2018accompanying\u2019 them.\u201d57<\/u><\/sup> The pattern of the call to commitment coming from outside the anthropologist, indeed, from her research subjects, is not unique to Scheper-Hughes. We have already seen how this is the case with Bourgois. Dana-Ain Davis writes of her own situation, \u201cSherita asked me what I was going to do with all of the information I collected. She made it very clear that she was only a \u2018case file\u2019 at social services and that it was my responsibility to tell \u2018people\u2019 how difficult life was and share the problems women faced while on welfare\u2026 My work as a politically engaged anthropologist began at that moment.\u201d58<\/u> <\/sup>In other words, Sherita was asking Davis, like Otim asked me, that her research not be another instance of cultural plunder.<\/p>\n Scheper-Hughes decides to join the Brazilian women, and doing so shifts her understanding of her discipline. \u201cIf we cannot begin to think about social institutions and practices in moral or ethical terms,\u201d she writes, \u201cthen anthropology strikes me as quite weak and useless.\u201d In her 1995 article, \u201cThe Primacy of the Ethical: Propositions for a Militant Anthropology,\u201d she, like Bourgois, makes the de-romanticization of other cultures the core of her argument: \u201cWhat draws me back to these people and places is not their exoticism and their \u2018otherness\u2019 but the pursuit of those small spaces of convergence, recognition, and empathy that we share. Not everything dissolves into the vapor of absolute cultural difference and radical otherness.\u201d Scheper-Hughes replaces the idea of \u201cradical otherness\u201d with that of \u201csolidarity,\u201d a concept that recognizes the distinctiveness of other cultures while also affirming sufficient points of similarity for some mutual recognition and cooperative action.59<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n The recognized points of inter-cultural connection enabled by the de-exoticization of others and the resultant affirmation of an ethics of solidarity allows, even requires, the anthropologist to make, when called for, value judgments about the persons she studies. Scheper-Hughes dramatically illustrates this point by telling of her intercession in the disciplining of some thieves in the Chris Hani camp\u2014a South African shanty town\u2014in 1993. The camps resisted policing by the white security forces because of the latter\u2019s many brutalities. Therefore, members of the camps attempted to police themselves. Without a written or strong oral basis for self-regulation, the communities administered their versions of justice in uneven and often capricious ways. In Chris Hani, three boys were caught stealing 400 rands (about 125 dollars). Quickly a crowd gathered that was going to \u201cnecklace\u201d the boys. Necklacing is the practice of putting a tire full of gasoline around the neck of a person and setting it on fire, a modern form of witch-burning. Members of the ANC intervened and got the punishment reduced to fifty lashes. As a continuation of the discipline, the boys were not allowed to eat or drink. Fearing that the smallest of them was going to die, Scheper-Hughes, knowing that she could not do so openly, sneaked a doctor into the holding cell to check on him and then secretly evacuated him to a hospital.<\/p>\n Scheper-Hughes is aware that solidarity with one\u2019s research subjects, particularly if they are marginalized persons, yields risks. After taking the smallest thief to the hospital, she received an anonymous phone call: \u201c\u2018Stay away from Chris Hani camp,\u2019 the heavily-accented brown-Afrikaner voice warned. \u2018People there are angry that you interfered with their discipline. Your safety cannot be guaranteed.\u2019\u201d60<\/u><\/sup> However, she returned to the camp, and her testimony in a communal meeting helped change the camp\u2019s disciplinary practices. Here, already, her actions closely parallel those of the two priests in Magwi in the scenario above: she recognizes that, given the social context, she is in all likelihood the only one with the power to act in the way she did.<\/p>\n Indeed, when she attempts to articulate her commitment, Scheper-Hughes calls her actions \u201cwitness,\u201d and it is here that she comes closest to recognizing her convergence with a discipline that anthropology has long rejected. She writes, \u201cIt is the act of \u2018witnessing\u2019 that lends our work its moral, at times almost theological, character.\u201d This is because to speak and act in light of the \u201cprimacy of the ethical\u201d is to \u201csuggest\u201d certain \u201ctranscendent\u201d grounds for moral norms.61<\/u><\/sup> Bourgois is similar in his appeal to human rights that transcend specific cultures, and even more so when the horror of the atrocities prompt him to conclude by describing the victims in terms with deep theological resonances: \u201cWe should not forget that our \u2018informants\u2019 continue to be crucified.\u201d62<\/u><\/sup><\/p>\n I am not at all suggesting here that anthropologists become theologians, or that their concerns about the history of oppression at the hands of Christianity are without merit. These concerns are mine as well. Rather, I am suggesting that situations of extreme violence and risk often press anthropologists, if they answer their research subjects\u2019 calls to join in solidarity, to interpretive language that finds significant points of contact with a committed Christianity, and that conversation ought to take place between these two groups for its own sake and for the sake of the oppressed.<\/p>\n The parallels between Scheper-Hughes\u2019s and Pope John Paul II\u2019s understanding of such solidarity are striking. In John Paul\u2019sSollicitudo rei Socialis<\/em> (English title, \u201cOn Social Concern\u201d), solidarity has three aspects to it. The first is simply the descriptive fact of human interconnectedness. Solidarity is \u201ca question of interdependence, sensed as a system determining relationships in the contemporary world, in its economic, cultural, political, and religious elements.\u201d Secondly, however, awareness of interdependence can and ought to spawn concern that the relationships between and among peoples are shaped for the good. Interdependence must be accepted as a \u201cmoral category.\u201d Noteworthy here is John Paul\u2019s warning against abstractness and his insistence that solidarity should be grounded in encounters with specific people. Solidarity \u201cis not a feeling of vague compassion or shallow distress at the misfortunes of so many people, both near and far. On the contrary, it is a firm and persevering determination to commit oneself to the common good; that is to say to the good of all and of each individual, because we are all really responsible for all.\u201d63<\/u><\/sup> Again, the Magwi priests act on the part of the people because no one else can. Third and finally, when solidarity has a transcendent referent, it exemplifies itself in one\u2019s willingness to sacrifice one\u2019s own life for others, even for one\u2019s enemy. The following paragraph illuminates most fully Father Joseph\u2019s willingness to join Father Maurice in riding the motorcycle towards the LRA.<\/p>\n In the light of faith, solidarity seeks to go beyond itself…One\u2019s neighbor must therefore be loved, even if an enemy, with the same love with which the Lord loves him or her; and for that person\u2019s sake one must be ready for sacrifice, even the ultimate one: to lay down one\u2019s life for the brethren.64<\/u><\/sup><\/p><\/blockquote>\n If we turn to Scheper-Hughes\u2019s account of solidarity, we find strong analogues to each of the three aspects or moments in John Paul II\u2019s treatment. First, there is an acknowledgment and even affirmation of human interdependence and commonality. Again, \u201cWhat draws me back to these people and places is not their exoticism and their \u2018otherness\u2019 but the pursuit of those small spaces of convergence\u2026 Not everything dissolves into the vapor of absolute cultural difference and radical otherness.\u201d Like John Paul, Scheper-Hughes takes this recognition of connectedness as an occasion for commitment. In her words, \u201cIf we cannot begin to think about social institutions and practices in moral or ethical terms, then anthropology strikes me as quite weak and useless.\u201d Her accounts of her work in Brazil and South Africa provide precisely the kind of specificity that John Paul points to when he speaks of solidarity as a \u201cfirm and persevering\u201d commitment to \u201cthe good of all and of each individual.\u201d Finally, in her actions on behalf of the thieves, we have a love of enemy even to the point of the willingness to risk one\u2019s life. It is at this point that her actions and those of the priests in Magwi converge most forcefully: if the man who made the anonymous phone call or one of his accomplices kills Scheper-Hughes, at least one of the imprisoned boys will have more time to get away.<\/p>\n If we are to follow Scheper-Hughes and John Paul II, then we must insist that the witness of both engaged anthropology and an authentic Christianity involve, when the situation calls for it, the willingness to risk our lives. This does not mean that we do not use phronesis or practical wisdom in assessing risk. The aim is solidarity, not risk itself. Still, a life where risk \u2014 real bodily risk \u2014 on behalf of solidarity is never at stake raises questions about the commitment to solidarity. As John Paul II points out, oppression is structural violence; if we never become exposed to the violence, then this is an indication that our commitment is questionable. Willingness, or what John Paul calls \u201creadiness\u201d to risk, is a mark\u2014even if it is not the only one\u2014of commitment to love one\u2019s neighbor. Scheper-Hughes\u2019s actions exemplify John Paul II\u2019s claim in Veritatis Splendor<\/em> that martyrdom\u2014or even the willingness to lay down one\u2019s life\u2014\u201cconfirms\u201d moral truths in \u201ca particularly eloquent way.\u201d It is the \u201chigh point of witness to moral truth.\u201d65<\/u><\/sup> In other words, in moving from the particulars of a person\u2019s life in a specific cultural setting to broad claims about the human dignity and rights of all people, virtue theory insists that we reason with our bodies as well as with our words. What we gain from the conversation between engaged anthropology and committed Christianity is the insight that perhaps the most elegant argument for human rights is a life of a certain sort well-lived, and, as a result, a willingness, when the circumstances call for it, to let that life go for the sake of someone else and something more.<\/p>\n I have made the case for a kind of anthropology that recognizes the fallacy of the fact\/value separation and does not shrink from a more robust commitment to its research subjects, drawing upon the traditions of virtue theory to give that commitment shape and direction. I have also argued that anthropology should engage committed Christians in conversation about the outer edges of the risks involved in such a venture. The history of anthropologists and Christians in the field is not, for the most part, one of friendship, and it is at this point that the directive to love, or at least talk to, our enemies is most poignant. This we should do above all for the sake of those whose good we claim to seek: those who are crushed\u2014in Bourgois\u2019 words, \u201ccrucified\u201d\u2014by the powerful and the vicious. If we undertake this task of conversation and cooperation, we will soon find that our energies, even joined, are not sufficient, and that we will need to extend the effort even further to other groups and communities, religious and otherwise.<\/p>\n Photo by K. Burns [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons.<\/em><\/p>\n \u00a0<\/p>\n
\nThe Limits of Cultural Relativism<\/strong><\/h3>\n
The Virtues of Virtue Theories<\/strong><\/h3>\n
(An Attempt to Live) The Virtue of Solidarity<\/strong><\/h3>\n
Anthropological Solidarity and Christian Charity<\/strong><\/h3>\n
Conclusion: Broadening the Conversation<\/strong><\/h3>\n
\nNotes<\/h4>\n
\n